Vacation
Yours faithfully,
Dasein-Toni
I will read through Heidegger's Being and Time, one of the most difficult philosophical books ever produced, and share my sentiments as I follow it through to its (bitter?) end.
Part I, Chapter I, §§9-11
The first chapter intends to expose the existential analysis of Dasein and to show how this relates to other similar studies.
§9
First Heidegger states that we will here analyse that being that we ourselves always are: Dasein, “here-being” or “there-being”. This sort of being, Dasein, has a relation to its own being: to it its being is like something. According to Heidegger, this brings forth two things:
(1) The essence of this being is included in that it must be. Therefore the what-being (essence) of Dasein is to be determined from its being (existence), if we wish to speak of essence at all. Therefore Dasein’s essence is not in its properties, but in its way of being, it’s mode of being. I think this is to be taken as saying that the essence of man is not any set of properties, but in the way man is: as something that has the ability to have a view on its own being, to question it and to try to understand it. Dasein does not, therefore, express some object such as a table, but a way in which something is – no matter what the actual object that has this mode of being happens to be. I take this to mean that a computer can be Dasein, if it can question its own being, and a human can be non-Dasein, and actually is just that when turned into a corpse (or a vegetable - like me).
(2) Dasein is always my being. I take this to mean not that Heidegger is saying that all Daseins are him, but that of every Dasein we must use a personal pronoun: me, you, him etc. Basically, I understand this as a similar thing to Kant’s Transcendental Unity of Apperception, that is, the necessary condition for a subject to be a subject is that he is able to say “I think” of every perception that he has. Heidegger is saying, I believe, that every Dasein can say of himself that “I am”, so to speak. Every Dasein is “I”, for himself. Heidegger then differentiates between Dasein and Vorhandensein, that being a sort of “present-to-hand-being”, as it is sometimes translated. Things that are not Dasein can be present to hand, that is, as something that is before us, accessible and present - a mere object that cannot be a subject. To these present-to-hand-beings their being is irrelevant (as it is, assumably, irrelevant to a table that it exists). But for Dasein, as explained before, his being cannot be irrelevant.
Heidegger says that Dasein is always its own possibility. This possibility is not something it owns like something that is present-to-hand. It is not an object. This possibility is Dasein. But what does Heidegger mean by “possibility”? In the introduction we saw that possibility for Heidegger is something that the Dasein can be. This is: the horizon it sees before itself. I think that I can be a philosopher. It is possible for me, and it is something that I can reach. I can become a philosopher, if I choose to. Now the totality of these possibilities is for Heidegger the Dasein’s possibility, and this possibility is what the Dasein is – of course, this Dasein is a particular Dasein, like me, not Dasein in general. Dasein is in the world, with all his desires, dreams, wants and principles. This totality of what the Dasein sees is his possibility, and it is this totality that determines what the particular Dasein is. In non-Heideggerian: I am the totality of my dreams, beliefs, desires, thoughts and so on and so on. That is, as me. Of course, I am also a body, but that body is not the Dasein. When I speak of me, I speak of me-as-a-subject: me-as-a-Dasein. It is not, for Heidegger, just that I have dreams and beliefs, but that I am those. This is a strong claim, but I think it holds. As long as this “possibility” is defined broadly enough (as it is now: it is simply the totality of all that I consider myself to be in relation with), it spans the whole of my subjectivity. And as a subject, I am these subjective notions. As an object I might be a body, but as a subject I am something that has a relation to his body. I think of my body in a certain way. This which in me thinks of things in a certain way is the Dasein.
It should be made clear that this is in a sense Heidegger’s philosophy of mind. Heidegger seems to think that being a subject is simply to “be there”, to have a relation to where one is. This returns us directly to the common notion that for a subject, for a consciousness, things are like something. For a table the floor on which it stands is not like anything, but for me it is. This like-being, so to speak, is not something that the object itself has, but what the subject projects to it. Therefore Heidegger says that being a conscious subject is to have this like-relation to things. And what is then this subject? It is the totality of these like-relations. Why? Perhaps – I am just speculating here – because if we take away all these like-relations, what do we have left? Nothing at least that would make the thing we are left with conscious (there is nothing that is like something to it). Perhaps the only thing that he has is the potentiality of being in like-relation to something. That is, the Dasein. Is the Dasein then the necessary condition for being a subject? An impersonal subjectivity? Those of you that know of these things must have already guessed what I am aiming at: is the Dasein the transcendental subject? That same limit of subjectivity that for Kant was the transcendental subject, for Wittgenstein the eye, and for Husserl the transcendental ego? It seems plausible.
But I am not through with Heidegger's philosophy of mind yet. What is known as Brentano’s thesis is that being a subject is about being an intentional being – that is, having intentional states of mind. Intentionality means having a certain directed relation to things. Basically: my states of mind are directed at things. Either things within my consciousness, within my body or totally external to me. Is Heidegger an intentionalist? I cannot see why he would not be. After all, the whole point of Dasein is that he can ask questions. What are questions? They are something that have the one who asks it (the subject) and the question itself that is directed to something of which it is asked (the object). This ability to ask questions is then equivalent with the ability to have a certain directed relation to objects. Also, the like-relation is such a relation: something (object) is like something to something (subject). The being-like-something is intentional, because the state of mind is directed at an object of which the being-like-something is said. I think this is enough to prove that Heidegger is an intentionalist. Let the demons of the Citadel Being and Time strike me down, if they will to oppose my judgment!
In any case, it is important to understand that for Dasein existence comes before essence (Heidegger is an existentialist) - because the essence is a way of being - and that it is always egocentric (this has unwanted connotations – it would perhaps be better to say me-centred).
Heidegger says that Dasein must be exposed through existential analysis of its existence (that is, through analysing the formal structure of Dasein’s existence), but in this we must not start by postulating a certain kind of existence, but we must start from the vague generality of Dasein’s existence: averageness. This everyday averageness of Dasein is the foundation of its ontic being (ontic, remember, was about things that are, in opposition to the way things are in general), and as such it is the closest to us in the ontic sense. But that which is closest to us ontically is the furthest away from us ontologically (That which is closest to us has a structure that is hardest to determine, because we cannot detach ourselves from it to see it in its totality) . Therefore, according to Heidegger, this averageness can now be “passed by”. I am rather baffled at this. Reading again and again what Heidegger is saying about this does not make it any clearer, to my utter annoyance. It seems to me that Heidegger might be trying to say that the averageness is something that we always are, but what is not something directly associated with the structure of being. That is, averageness is a name for all the vague additional stuff in our lives that obstructs our being, even though it is in a sense a foundation for our being (in the ontic sense). But this does not open up for me, and I will have to look at this later, if I can.
Nonetheless, the explications gained from analysing Dasein are called existentials. They are the ways Dasein can be – in this they share a relation to categories (for Aristotle: ways for objects to be, for Kant: ways to think of objects). Therefore existentials are the specific ways in which the Dasein is – apart from other beings. Categories explicate the ways non-Dasein-beings can be. For Heidegger existentials and categories are both the fundamental possibilities for things to be. The existentials pertain to beings that are who (existence) and categories to beings that are what (being present-at-hand in general – objects). How these two are related together can be resolved only after the horizon of asking the question about being has been uncovered.
§10
We come by two metal doors on both sides of the corridor. Looking at my fellows for support, I swallow and turn the handle on the door on the right side.
The door opens silently and reveals a horrid sight. The special sciences known as Anthropology, Psychology and Biology are caged in a room filled with torturing devices. On the wall it reads in letters of blood: "The special sciences work within the Being and cannot explain it. Thus as slaves to Fundamental Analysis of Dasein, they must forever succumb to my rule." In horror I realize that these poor bastards are of no use in finding the meaning of Being and are therefore abandoned in this torturing chamber of particular sciences. The meaning of Being can only be exposed through fundamental analysis on the existentiality of Dasein, and never through the special sciences that only explicate empirical matters within the framework of existentiality of Dasein. I hastily close the door, grieving for the fate of these sciences.
§11
As I open the other door, I find myself face to face with another torturing chamber. I hear some muffled screams about the difference between primitivity (as studied in anthropology and ethnology, a level of sophistication of a culture) and averageness. A bloody iron maiden of “natural world” (which has been at least in part constructed by the Dasein himself) is also seen in the corner. I feel sick, and gagging I close the door and hope that the next corridor will expose something else than mere cruelty of massacred empirical sciences.
While examining the gothic inscriptions on the wall of the antechamber, I find a copper plate on the wall. At first it looks blank, but soon I begin to recognize very fine lines in the shining surface, almost too insignificant to notice. Unable to decipher the curves, I call Tobi-Ass to my aid. He examines the plate for a while and then nods slightly. “I know what this is: it contains arcane knowledge on Heideggerian terminology. It is normally only readable to Heideggerian initiates, and I am surprised to find out that you could even make out the lines, even if not uncover their meaning. Heidegger must have a stronger hold on you that you would perhaps care to admit. Mmm. I know how to deal with this. Stand back!”
I step back hastily and watch as Tobi-Ass sets his cheek (well, asses have no hands, but asses do have cheeks. He can’t use his hoofs, now can he? Oh, well, come to think of it, he could, but that wouldn't be nearly as fun. And considering how unfunny this is, it is best that he sets his cheek instead of his hoof...) against the plate and whispers softly: “Ich habe ein Bratwurst in meine Lederhose”. I hold my breath.
Nothing happens. Kant and Wittgenstein share glances - apparently they know something that I don't... probably has something to do with their mastery of the foul language Tobi-Ass has been forced to learn in his studies of Dialectical Necromancy. Tobi-Ass coughs nervously and murmurs: “Blah. That was of course the secret entrance code for the even more secret organization of snowunicorns, how could I forget.” He then sets his cheek again on the plate and speaks in a clear, loud voice: “Nacktfrosch”.
The plate immediately starts shimmering and letters of fire emerge to fill the surface. “There you go, Dasein-Toni”, Tobi-Ass declares proudly, and a lump in my throat I shuffle nearer and immerse myself in the secrets of the plate.
Introduction, Part II, §§7-8
§7
In the beginning of the seventh clause, Heidegger explains that we must now explicate the method used in studying the meaning of Being. That is, the method of ontology. As Heidegger’s ontology differs from every other kind of conception of ontology, he states that this method should not be looked for in the history of philosophy. Then he states that the method must be that of phenomenology. Also, it is important to note that phenomenology is not an aspect or a field of philosophy, but a mere method: it only explicates how the study is conducted, not what is studied.
What is phenomenology? I am fully aware that I am on a thin ice here, for my arcane knowledge on the occult magic of phenomenology is rather limited. Heidegger himself is at this point so vague, that I start to wonder if even he knows! He says that phenomenology is a maxim (I kick Kant’s ankle sharply and he whispers: “a subjective law, or a principle!”) that could be expressed by the slogan: “Into the things themselves!” Okay, Heidegger, sounds classy, but what do you mean? He explicates that phenomenology does not accept any principle that is not conclusively proven, and it opposes pseudo-questions that prevail through generations. As soon as I exclamate that this is what all sciences purport to do, he himself admits that someone could say that. Indeed! And what does he do then? Nothing. Or, not exactly true: he says that we are in fact dealing with such self-evidencies, and that he is just explicating the preliminary idea of phenomenology here. Well, all fine and dandy, Heidegger – at least now I know that phenomenology adheres to the same principles as any other science that should be taken seriously.
But I have not slept through all of my phenomenology classes (Actually, I have not slept through any of my phenomenology classes, because I have never had any). Phenomenology is something that concerns itself with what is experienced. That is, it analyses our experiences. Everything in phenomenology should be directly based on experience, or should be reduced through proven steps to something that is thusly founded. The exact details are not of importance in our preliminary examination: I think it is enough to understand that as we found out in the former clauses, the study must start from the everyday existence of Dasein, and therefore it must be based on the way Dasein experiences the world it lives in. This, of course, gives direct justification for choosing the method of phenomenology.
Heidegger states that the word phenomenology translates directly as “science of the phenomena”, that is, as a science that studies appearances, or how things appear to us. He then sets to explain the two constituent words of phenomenology, phenomenon and logos, in a more detailed manner.
A. The concept of phenomenon
He throws a lot of Greek on my face in an attempt to either explain in detail what he is speaking of, or to put me off balance. In any case, the basic idea that can be found within the lesson on Greek is clear: phenomenon means something that shows/presents itself or is evident. But Heidegger also notes that something can appear either as something that it is, or as something that it is not, depending on the aspect we take to it. “It appears that the tyre is flat” expresses “appearance” in a positive sense (we think that it is rather clear that the tyre is indeed flat), or “It appeared to be solid, but in fact it wasn’t” expresses “appearance” in a negative sense (something appeared as it really was not). We could also explicate the difference through the English word “to seem”, which holds similar connotations. In any case, the word phenomenon then includes the idea that something can appear to us either as it is, or as it is not.
He also explains at length how such terms as “express” or “imply” or some such bear a relation to “appear”. Such a case would be symptoms of a disease, where the disease that itself does not appear is expressed by the symptoms, or that the symptoms imply the disease that itself does not appear. This is not appearing in the negative sense, because that which does not appear at all, cannot either appear as it is or as it is not. So even though different sorts of indications share the structure of appearance, they must still be distinguished from each other.
The next part is nigh unintelligible. That is okay, I think, because Heidegger himself expresses that this is a source of a lot of confusion. Nonetheless, I will try to explain the different ways for things to appear.
(1) Something can appear as it is, or as it is not. In this the thing is somehow present, but can be distorted.
(2) Something appears only through sort of symptoms or indications. In these cases the thing is not itself present at all (it does not appear in the sense of (1)), but something indicates it, points to it. This way of appearing can be divided into three different senses:
(2. 1.) Something “lets itself be heard/known”. It appears in the sense that things that point to it are manifest, but it itself is hidden. Diseases are mostly like this, for example.
(2. 2.) Something appears as an indicator itself. The symptoms of a disease are like this: their appearance implies something that does not itself appear, that is, lets itself be heard (very Heideggerian. Tsk, tsk, Dasein-Toni!).
(2. 3.) Something appears so as to both indicate something, and to hide that which is indicated. This is difficult to understand at first, but Heidegger points nicely to Kant. This makes it clear that the appearances as used by Kant mean appearances in this sense (although according to him Kant confused the different meanings from time to time): they are appearances of the Ding an sich, the thing in itself, but even though they in a sense express the things in themselves, they also hide them. That-which-lets-itself-be-heard is cloaked by that-which-is-heard, so to speak. Thus instead of speaking of “appearances”, we should say “mere appearances”.
Heidegger pulls the threads together (phew!) in a rather nice way. If we consider the word phenomenon, it holds within it a manifold: appearance (1), presentation (2.1.), manifestation (2.2.) and mere manifestation (2.3.). Manifestation could also be translated as expression, for example. As a synopsis: appearance is something that is itself present, either like it really is, or like something else (in which case the term deception could perhaps be used). Presentation is something that is itself not present, but is presented or indicated by something: for example a disease. Manifestation is that-which-presents some presentation, that is, for example, the symptoms of a disease. Mere manifestation is a manifestation that simultaneously presents or indicates something and hides it (so that it cannot be found even in principle).
As a closing remark, Heidegger states that the phenomenon in the sense it is used in phenomenology differs from the usage of appearance in the common speech. What is appearance in common speech, for Heidegger? Simply our perceptions. I take this to mean that for Heidegger phenomenology is not a science about perceptions, but about something rather different, although interconnected. What that is, is expressed above in (1)-(2). We will now turn to the concept of logos.
B. The concept of logos
Logos means “speech”. It is also, according to Heidegger, translated as reason, proposition, concept, definition, foundation or relation. This shows that the concept of logos is horribly vague. Heidegger purports to find the foundation of the word to explain how the ambiguous term “speech” could be defined so as to include or derive all these other meanings.
Heidegger states that logos as “speech” should be understood more like as making it evident what the speech is about. Logos brings something forth that is seen by the speaker to be seen by all that take part in the discussion. This becomes clear, when it is understood that when I speak something – as I do now, even though through text – I speak of something that appears to me, and labour to express it so that those that listen to me could see that same thing. So Heidegger distinguishes between that which is said from that which the speech is about. You see what is said, but that does not always suffice for you to see what the speech is about. This seems to me like a more general conception of word and its referent. Heidegger also notes that acts of speech such as praying or begging bring forth that which is seen by the speaker, but in a slightly different way. This “bringing forth” Heidegger labels as “to make evident”. “I have an itch” makes evident that I have an itch, even though this analytical way of putting this probably doesn’t do justice to Heidegger.
But logos also makes something evident as something. This takes Heidegger to his conception of truth, for logos can either be true or false. As true it brings something forth in a way that it becomes unhidden – it makes it evident as unhidden. As false it brings that something forth in a way that it becomes obstructed. But, Heidegger goes on: this is not what truth really means; truth is something linked with our perceptions. Truth is not a property of a proposition, but a property of perception. Perception is true in this sense if it shows something like it is, and false if it does not. This is, of course, diagonally opposed to almost every modern conception of truth, that take truth to be a property of a proposition, that is, as something that belongs to reason, not perception. I will not explicate Heidegger’s idea further, because it would take us far too deep into modern truth theories. But I will, nonetheless, offer a link (that is, a teleport to a pocket dimension) a short explication of what Heidegger means by truth: http://www.mv.helsinki.fi/home/tkannist/thoughts/heidegger.htm.
Heidegger ends the presentation by noting that logos is synthesis whenever it is not pure, direct understanding of perceptions. (That is, I assume, always.) By synthesis he does not as much mean linking together as bringing something forth as something, that is, in connection with something else. This is highly Kantian, even though Heidegger to some extent denies this. For Kant logos without synthesis would appear when some being could directly perceive objects as they are (Kant actually speaks of such a possible being in theory – and notes that God would be such a being, if He exists). All the cognition available for humans is synthesis for Kant, that is, based on forming concepts from perceptions. This means that particular perceptions are synthesised into concepts that are sort of generalisations. Heidegger does not stray far when he speaks of synthesis as being-in-connection: when we understand something as something, we always in a sense put it in relation with other things and judge that it bears resemblance to some things, and does not to others. This connection to Kant is made clear, when we take an example: I see a red car. That red car is seen by me as something, that is, as red and as a car. Because that particular object is for me red, it is then something that in a sense takes part in the concept “red” (and the same applies to being a car). To see the car as red is to see it in relation to at least other colours: not seeing it as e.g. blue.
The important thing to understand here is that synthesis always offers a possibility of obstruction. This is clear: when I see the object as a car, I can either be right in seeing it as a car, or be in error. It might, after all, be a huge turnip that appears as a car (or, it should be said: imposes as a car). But when I see the thing directly, not as something, I cannot be in error. This is also evident in the Kantian interpretation: God cannot err, because there is nothing he could make an error of!
As a conclusion, Heidegger offers some ways to derive the other meanings of logos from this original conception of logos as bringing forth or making evident in speech. There is nothing particularly interesting there, but the understanding that Heidegger thinks the other meanings indeed follow.
C. Preliminary conception of phenomenology
In this last section Heidegger pulls together the results of A and B. He first notes that there seems to be an inner relation between phenomenon and logos. Through analysis of the word “phenomenology” he ends up with the definition: phenomenology brings forth through itself that which appears as it in itself appears.
Huh? What sense to make of this? I must admit, that Heidegger’s use of words here is of no use to me. Perhaps I would fare better if I tried to derive the meaning of phenomenology myself through what I understand of phenomenon and logos? It is worth the attempt, I guess. Now logos brings forth something that is seen by the speaker. Phenomenon is an appearance, or that which appears. Phenomenology should then apparently bring forth phenomena, those that appear. But I believe that phenomenon here means also to appear as itself (as something that is like itself, more precisely). So in this interpretation, phenomenology brings forth those that appear as themselves to appear as they are themselves. I think this is at least close to what Heidegger says above, so I am carefully confident that I got the idea. Could I perhaps, then, somehow express this idea so that it would be understood? (Hah, a nice example of what we spoke of in the presentation of logos). Well, I can try.
Phenomenology is the study of appearances. Appearances are something that are not only perceptions, but some things that present themselves in some way – either as themselves or as not themselves. I have a lot of these appearances: the computer screen before appears to me like a computer screen (of course, it might not be one), for example. Phenomenology would then study these appearances. But how? By bringing these appearances forth into objective discourse. But bringing forth was to bring forth as something. As what does phenomenology attempt to bring forth these appearances? As themselves, that is, as appearances! Phenomenology studies appearances as appearances, not as something else. It does not study appearances as psychology does (as manifestations of some deeper level activity), but simply as appearances themselves. So it is made evident what Heidegger said before: phenomenology has no specific subject matter, but it is a method. It does not matter what the appearances are about, because phenomenology simply studies the appearances, not the things they present, or manifest, or whatever. I hope this is clear enough.
What is phenomenology suppose to “bring forth”? What is that which is to be called “phenomenon”? Reading this part again and again, I scratch my head in confusion. Could it be that Heidegger is saying, that the “phenomenon” itself is something that is present in all appearing, something that is necessarily indicated by all appearances? (Remember, this is (2.1.).) It seems plausible. This would explain why Heidegger turns so suddenly from phenomenon to Being. It seems that Heidegger has found the connection he needed: that which is indicated by all things that are, is the being of Being itself. Being is manifested (2.2.) through particular modes of being, or simply through things that are. And so Heidegger comes to the conclusion that what phenomenology is ultimately studying is Being itself and states: “Ontology is possible only as phenomenology”. (Remember that ontology bears special meaning for Heidegger).
I must say, that this is remarkable. The sheer complexity of the structure Heidegger builds is formidable, and yet he manages to tie the knots in a rather beautiful way. Assuming, that I understood what he was trying to say. I am truly beginning to like this man who demands so much of one’s brains, forces one to think until steam arises from one’s ears, but in the end also gives a lot. Not only has he managed to point of evident flaws in the foundations of our thinking, the vacuity of conceptions like “being”, but he has also, at least this far, managed to give plausible answers. He is difficult to understand simply because he thinks so differently, and forces one to think differently too. It is always difficult to learn another way of thinking (consider learning mathematics or logic for the first time). But when one learns to navigate, in a sense learns to swim in the new ocean, it starts to feel natural. I only hope that I have not already lost my touch in reality, and already speak in Heideggerian so that my words are incomprehensible. In some cases it is understandable because of the sheer complexity of the ideas I am trying to express, but it cannot be continuous. It cannot be a habit. Cold shivers run down my spine: have I become so immersed in the spell that is Being and Time, that I cannot even recognize the threat anymore? I must focus, however, and so let us move forth to end our survey that today is exceptionally long.
Phenomenology is then the study of the being of Being – ontology. When ontology was considered before, it was understood that Dasein is the fundament from which we must set out. I do not understand where Heidegger gets this from, but it still sounds plausible: Phenomenology of Dasein is hermeneutics, that is, interpretation of itself. Dasein’s phenomenology is then about Dasein trying to understand itself through interpreting itself. From this Heidegger finds the last loose thread and ties it to his knot: hermeneutics is the analytics of existence’s existentiality. As we might remember, existence was about Dasein’s being as like something for itself. Existentiality concerns the structure or form of this Dasein’s consideration of itself as like something. Hermeneutics is then, I believe, a science that studies Dasein as it sees itself: interpretation of Dasein’s way of being in the world. What is Dasein’s way of being? Most prominently culture: literature, history, sciences.
So philosophy for Heidegger is phenomenological ontology that starts from hermeneutics of Dasein and from those foundations aims to the Being itself.
This ends our analysis of §7, which has been clearly the longest clause this far. I feel quite good, because I was expecting a real intellectual breakdown, but instead gained a whole lot of clarity. Either I am starting to understand what this book is all about, or I am finally becoming insane.
§8
The analysis of Being must start from a particular mode of being: Dasein. Through the historical analysis of Dasein, it is possible to set the horizon of the study that is the Being and Time, or so says Heidegger. He then ends the whole of Introduction by explaining the structure of the tome in short:
The first part studies Dasein’s relation to time and explicates time as a transcendental horizon for asking about Being. (Transcendental horizon would mean that the necessary condition of asking about Being is the study of Dasein’s relation to time.) It divides into three questions:
(1) The preliminary fundamental analysis of Dasein.
(2) Dasein and temporality.
(3) Time and Being (Very clever to switch the order…)
The second part uses the method of phenomenological destruction of the history of ontology. It also divides into three sections:
(1) Kant’s (Woohoo!) ideas of schematism and time as the first step of the problematic of temporality.
(2) Descartes’s Cogito Sum’s ontological priming and the connection of Medieval ontology to the problematic of res cogitans (That would, as far as my Latin is concerned, a thinking being/thing).
(3) Aristotle’s study of time as a method of seeing the phenomenological foundations and limits of the ontology of Antique.
So, I have crawled through the endless ideas hurled at me during my journey through the entrance hall and its corridors that lead to the antechamber of the citadel that is Being and Time. Through the copper plate, with the assistance of Tobi-Ass the Dialectical Necromancer, I have interpreted the keys to the halls of the citadel. And one by one, we shall enter these halls to find the truths they have hidden. The journey will be long and arduous, I am sure, yet my initial success has given me courage. There is sense to be made here, no doubt. With the help of my newfound (and newly gravedigged) friends, we shall see our quest through and escape the Citadel of Being and Time with the well-guarded truths that it harbours deep within its endless corridors and vast halls.
I have now travelled through the corridor that leads from the entrance to the antechamber of Being and Time. I have both gained great insight, and experienced utter confusion. I have understood the terminology of Heidegger to some extent, and in the process started to speak in Heideggerian as well. The spell that is the Being and Time is potent indeed, and I must take better care not to fall totally under its influence. The tome twists my mind into this and that direction, leading me on to believe that I understand, and then in a single show of power strike me into spinning amidst the endless maze of concepts. Is this the good cop – bad cop strategy at work here? You know that one where the bad cop intimidates the interrogated and then the good cop steps in, so that the contrast is made clear. This has been noted to work: the interrogated will succumb to the good cop after being treated by the bad cop, simply because he is so relieved. Perhaps Being and Time is doing the same thing?
I do not know. There is yet the antechamber before me, and in there perhaps things will become clear at last.
On the door to the antechamber there is a picture of a snake turning onto itself, eating its own tail and forming a circle. This I recognize as the ancient, mythical Oroborus. Perhaps it is chosen as the sign of this place, for it seems to me that Being is like this serpent. It is not only a mere circle, but its own meaning turns back onto itself – its whole essence is that of an endless circle, where one can travel on forever. The true Being cannot be seen from within the circle, for one will only see endless repeat, questions turning back into themselves in a never ending cycle. The truth of Being, the essence of it, is only understood as the circle itself. Perhaps this makes sense, perhaps not. I put my musings aside, and turn the handle of the door to the antechamber and enter, fearful of what will await me there.
§5
In the preceding clauses Heidegger purported to show that examination of Dasein is primary to examination of Being itself. Now the problem then naturally arises: how to examine the Dasein? First Heidegger notes that Dasein is ontically the nearest to us, but ontologically furthest away. What does he mean? Well, as we factually are the Dasein, we are not only close to it, but as close to it as we can get. Basically I think this can be analogized to our subjectivity, which is something that is present in everything we do, because we arethat subjectivity. But it too is ontologically the furthest away, because precisely due to this ontic closeness it is so difficult to see the structure of our subjectivity. What is it to be a subject? How to explain this, if one has no experience of ever being anything else? How does one set out to recognize that which is our subjectivity in our experience, to say what is it like? What is a colour like? Or an emotion? We are too close to Dasein to see it clearly.
And so Heidegger says that Dasein is trying to understand its own being through understanding what it is not, by reflecting on the non-Dasein, that being the world itself. The world is our mirror through which we try to understand ourselves. So it is only through that being into which the Dasein is always in relation (the world) that any understanding can arise. Dasein is always understood as being already in a relation to the world, and it is understood only through understanding this relation, and for each Dasein this relation is individual.
Heidegger says that we have a huge amount of different interpretations of Dasein at our disposal. He lists for example psychology, anthropology, ethics and history as such interpretations, and then asks whether the existential analysis of these fields is done carefully enough. By this he means that if these are ways to see the Dasein, have we sufficiently studied the structure of these ways: have we determined the foundations of these disciplines clearly enough to see how they really purport to explain Dasein?
Heidegger says, in my opinion, that Dasein should not be examined theoretically, but practically. It should be studied through examining its everyday mode of being. We must try to understand how Dasein really is in its everyday being – not idealise it through some semi-arbitrary theoretical structure. He then states that we shall find out that meaning of Dasein is its temporality. He does not explicate further what this means here; that will be done later. But instead he says that this interpretation of Dasein sets the foundation from which we stand a chance to find the answer to the meaning of Being in general.
Time is not time in its ordinary sense for Heidegger. (Surprise, surprise.) Time is that from which the Dasein attempts to understand itself. It is the horizon of interpretation of Being. I do not claim to understand what Heidegger is saying here, because I don’t believe it is understandable as of yet. But it seems that he is trying to get from the ordinary conception of time as a sort of dimension into a more fundamental conception: in which time is a sort of basis from which any understanding is possible. I will call this conception of time here Time, for it seems to me that there is still need for the ordinary sense of understanding time, for it is something that is derived from Time itself. I am not doing this to sound mystical, but only to differentiate between these two. I will also at times speak of Time as temporality. By this I try to express that this is not about certain moments of time, or how it expresses itself in reality, but about the phenomenon of Time in general, temporality. The basic difference Heidegger is explicating here is that between time itself and things that are in time. Form and content.
§6
DT: Ludwig?
W: Yes, Dasein-Toni?
DT: Is it true that your brother was a one-handed pianist?
W: Indeed it is, and a good one at that, I must add.
DT: It is just so strange to think of a one-handed pianist. Then again, I guess I am a one-handed pianist even though I have two hands, so perhaps the difference is just in the nature of the disability.
W: To some extent, yes, but we must bear in mind that even you, Dasein-Toni, could learn to play the piano with both hands, if you tried really hard.
DT: That was a nice thing to say, Big W.
W: My brother on the other hand, no pun intended, of course, didn’t manage to grow another arm as much as he tried.
DT: Pardon? Grow another arm? How would one go about doing something like that anyhow?
W: He used to sit hours in a corner staring out of the window, using his willpower to make it grow.
DT: You are pulling my leg.
W: No, no, it is true. Well, at least he used to sit in a corner doing something.
DT: But how do you know he was using willpower to grow his hand back? Did you ask?
W: No, I didn’t. You can’t really go to someone and ask: “So, huh, u usin' like ur willpa'wa to make ur arm gro' back on? Like, cool, huh huh.”
DT: Well, I am sure I too would have troubles to sound like Beavis and Butt-head.
W: Pardon?
DT: Ah, never mind. Just a facet of modern society you managed to miss by dying, that’s all.
W: I didn’t die.
DT: Oh, yes, sorry. You came here to look for your stolen ideas and got lost. We thought you did, though.
W: They are saying that I am dead?
DT: I am afraid so.
W: How intolerable! When I get back from this dump, I will set things straight.
DT: I am sure you will find Derrida delightful.
W: Who?
DT: Never mind. --- So, about your brother. Perhaps he was just looking out of the window? People do that sort of thing even when they have two hands.
W: Grmph. Perhaps you are right. Oh, well, but anyway. A fine pianist, nonetheless.
DT: I am sure. You know what’s weird, Witty, though?
W: That if you take a carrot and stick it in the forehead of a snowman, it still doesn’t look like a snow-unicorn.
DT: Uhh, yeah, okay, that’s weird, but I was thinking more of the fact that all notable one-handed pianists were left-handed pianists. If you calculate the odds, it simply doesn’t work. Although, there are not so many renown one-handed pianists in the world. It might be that either left hand is better for playing a piano (which would explain my lack of success, as I play on my right hand), or that as most people are right-handed, they tend to lose their right hand.
W: How come?
DT: Well, at least for me it works that way. Whenever I fall or stumble, my right hand reacts the fastest and gets the bruises. I nearly always end up with bruises in my right hand instead of left, so if there is an accident, perhaps it is more probable for the better arm to get smashed? And that would be, according to probabilities again, the right hand: leaving you as not only a one-handed pianist, but a left-handed at that.
W: Fascinating.
DT: Well, yeah. But that’s enough of that, I think. The last time you gave such a nice synopsis of what we went through before. Would you care to do one again, today? Yesterday ended with such a confusion, that a brief recollection would be in order.
W: Why, certainly, Dasein-Toni. Should there be any readers left, it would be good for them too, do you not think so?
DT: I surely would, if there were anyone reading. It is just so quiet and lonely down here. Eerie, even.
W: I know what you mean, Dasein-Toni. But endure we must, so on to the briefing.
DT: Ready when you are, Wittgenstein.
W: Right. In the clause §3 we ended up with the idea that all sciences are based on some axiomatic foundations, and that their value of progression is in their ability to cause crisis in those foundations. We also understood that all these foundations are parts taken from the most general Being, and that understanding this Being would be useful in two ways: in securing the foundations of particular sciences, and to produce new sciences altogether.
DT: That we did indeed, Witty. We also noted a connection to Kuhn that was interesting.
W: Who is Kuhn?
DT: Ah, I always forget that you di… went missing a half century ago. It’s just one guy.
W: Anyway, in clause §4 we plunged knee deep into shit.
DT: Wittgenstein!
W: Uh, sorry, but we did. Well, umm, found ourselves in dire straits indeed. Mr. Heidegger tried to explain to us his concepts of ontology, onticality, existentialism and existence, and to prove that Dasein was the most primary way of Being, through which all other ways are determined. I will try to explain briefly what is meant with these concepts.
Ontology:it deals with the structure of Being. It is not ontology in the common sense (that is, in the sense whether substances exist or what is causality), but a name for a discipline that tries to uncover the underlying structure of Being.
Onticality:this is about the things that are. Whereas ontology concerns the structure of Being, onticality studies things within that structure.
Existentialism: in the same way as above, this studies the structure of ways of Being, that is, existence. It is about the way existence manifests itself, how it is structured and how it functions, in a sense.
Existence: this was the trickiest of all. Existence seems to be a sort way of being only available for the Dasein, because it includes the ability to both see one's possibilities and reflect on themselves as well as to choose between the possibilities. It is the Dasein’s way of considering itself like something, and to affect this somethingness. It seems to be a common name for all the individual ways for the Dasein to perceive itself, and thus it is always in connection with the individuality in question. Existence is always determined in relation to the individual of whose existence it is about.
DT: Huh, those terms give me the creeps.
W: So do they to me. But with those we must dance, you and I. Let me just add that Heidegger’s conclusion was that Dasein is the most fundamental mode of being, because it is in special position both ontically (the only ontic being that can ask questions – in non-Heideggerian this would mean that they are the only entities in the universe that are able to ask questions, and they are privileged in that sense) and ontologically (the only being whose being is about its being – we are determined by our ability and desire to wonder about ourselves and our being). Dasein is then the ontic-ontological condition for ontology, as Heidegger put it. This is probably explained best by saying that Heidegger wants to express his idea that conscious beings (or beings that can ask) are the necessary condition for there to be any sensible structure to ontology at all (it is downright useless to ask about the structure of ontology without there being someone to ask about it – that is, Dasein).
DT: Fascinating, Witty. I think he, in a most perverse way, has a point there. I have pondered about the problematic of questions a lot lately, and it seems clear to me that answers hold no value, or indeed, no sense whatsoever without the questions. The question is primary, not the answer. Consider this answer: 2.718. What is the value of that? Quite simply: nothing before one explicates the question to which it is the answer. That is the approximate value of Napier-number e. (The exact value of this answer is known to all mathematicians and physicists, and I will not pursue it here.) Isn’t Heidegger simply saying that the answer to the meaning of Being can be considered sensible only if we explicate the question itself? Didn’t he actually say that in the beginning of the introduction, when he stated that we must first try to look at the question from a proper angle? Ah, I think I have indeed understood what Heidegger is maintaining here!
W: Fantastic, Dasein-Toni! And here we find another of the ideas that I lost!
DT: We did?
W: Sure. Do you remember that in Philosophical Investigations I pointed out that the concept of “the shortest way” is meaningless unless we first explicate where is it that we want to go, and from where?
DT: I do indeed. (After all, I am writing your lines too, you silly man.)
W: Well, that is all about the primacy of the question, again. The answers themselves only exist in relation to the questions. Of course, it could be argued that the objects that would become the answers do exist before the questions – like 2.718 was real before anyone asked about the Napier-number’s approximation. And I believe Heidegger is saying that, when he differentiates between the questioned and the object of the question. The object of question is impossible to reach unless the questioned is first set. That is, the things that would become the answers can exist without the questions, but they are answers only when a question is asked. Therefore Heidegger is saying that before we can even begin to seek the answer to the meaning of Being, we must first determine the exact question we are asking, and because only Dasein, that is, us, can ask questions, we must first ask: what is Dasein? Here is the primacy Heidegger purports to show.
DT: There is another question I would like to ask from you, Witty, if you don’t mind.
W: Shoot.
DT: “Shoot”?
W: I am trying to relate to the modern society and make my feeble attempts at not only to be Wittgenstein, but to be Cool-Wittgenstein.
DT: Oh dear.
K: You called?
DT: Ah, Kant! No, dear, go back into the pocket, I didn’t mean to call you.
K: Uhh, okay. Well, play with Wittgenstein then. I don’t mind. Really.
DT: Yeah, yeah. So, Wittgenstein: isn’t here another of your ideas manifest? I am referring to Heidegger’s apparent primacy of ethics – that after all is something you also attempted to say in the Tractatus, is it not?
W: Yes, it is indeed. In Lecture on Ethics I also express the primacy of ethics. In Tractatus I say that the world of the sad is a different world than the world of the happy. Not only does sadness change the way we see the world, it changes the world itself. This is ultimately because ethics and through them emotions, values and all those things are transcendent. They are not in the world, but beyond the world, determining the world. This is basically a rather Kantian notion, because it rests on the idea that the world we live in is a world-as-we-see-it, not the cognition-independent world. The transcendental subject is the eye, the border of the world that is the field of sight. If the world is a world of answers, then it is determined by the questions, and the questions are, in the end, something that arises from values, desires and ethics. Truly, ethics is primary to ontology. Through this it might be easier to understand why Heidegger says that Dasein is primary to ontology.
DT: Very interesting, thank you Witty. Not only am I starting to understand Heidegger, I am beginning to see how his philosophy fits the overall picture. And I just started the Being and Time. This has been a wonderful chat, and later on today we must travel onwards, to the second part of introduction that spans the clauses §§5-8. But first, let us rest a bit.
W: That would be prudent.